John Burnet
It is not very often that Plato allows himself to dwell on the history of philosophy as it was before the rise of ethical and epistemological inquiry; but when he does, he is always illuminating. His artistic gift and his power of entering into the thoughts of other men enabled him to describe the views of early philosophers in a sympathetic manner, and he never, except in a playful and ironical way, sought to read unthought-of meanings into the words of his predecessors. He has, in fact, a historical sense, which was a rare thing in antiquity.
The passage of the Phaedo (96a sqq.) where he describes the state of scientific opinion at Athens in the middle of the fifth century is invaluable for our purposes.
As a rule, Aristotle's statements about early philosophers are far less historical than Plato's. He nearly always discusses the facts from the point of view of his own system, and that system, resting as it does on the deification of the apparent diurnal revolution of the heavens, made it very hard for him to appreciate more scientific views. He is convinced that his own philosophy accomplishes what all previous philosophers had aimed at, and their systems are therefore regarded as "lisping" attempts to formulate it (Met. A, 10, 993 a 15). It is also to be noted that Aristotle regards some systems in a much more sympathetic way than others. He is distinctly unfair to the Eleatics, for instance, and in general, wherever mathematical considerations come into play, he is an untrustworthy guide.
It is often forgotten that Aristotle derived much of his information from Plato, and we must specially observe that he more than once takes Plato's humorous remarks too literally.
The Stoics, and especially Chrysippus, paid great attention to early philosophy, but their way of regarding it was simply an exaggeration of Aristotle's. They did not content themselves with criticizing their predecessors from their own point of view; they seem really to have believed that the early poets and thinkers taught doctrines hardly distinguishable from their own. The word sunoikeioun, which Cicero renders by accommodare, was used by Philodemus to denote this method of interpretation, which has had serious results upon our tradition, especially in the case of Heraclitus.
The same remarks apply mutatis mutandis to the Skeptics. The interest of such a writer as Sextus Empiricus in early philosophy is mainly to exhibit its contradictions. But what he tells us is often of value; for he frequently quotes early views as to knowledge and sensation in support of his thesis.
Under this head we have chiefly to consider the commentators on Aristotle in so far as they are independent of the Theophrastean tradition. Their chief characteristic is what Simplicius calls eugnômosunê, that is, a liberal spirit of interpretation, which makes all early philosophers agree with one another in upholding the doctrine of a Sensible and an Intelligible World. It is, however, to Simplicius more than any one else that we owe the preservation of the fragments. He had, of course, the library of the Academy at his disposal, at any rate up to A.D. 529.
The Doxographi Graeci of Professor Hermann Diels (1879) threw an entirely new light upon the filiation of the later sources; and we can only estimate justly the value of statements derived from these if we bear constantly in mind the results of his investigation. Here it will only be possible to give an outline which may help the reader to find his way in the Doxographi Graeci itself.
7. The "Opinions" of Theophrastus
By the term doxographers we understand all those writers who relate the opinions of the Greek philosophers, and who derive their material, directly or indirectly, from the great work of Theophrastus, Phusikôn doxôn iê (Diog. v. 46). Of this work, one considerable chapter, that entitled Peri aisthêseôn, has been preserved (Dox. pp. 499-527). And Usener, following Brandis, further showed that there were important fragments of it contained in the commentary of Simplicius (sixth cent. A.D.) on the First Book of Aristotle's Phusikê akroasis (Usener, Analecta Theophrastea, pp. 25 sqq.). These extracts Simplicius seems to have borrowed in turn from Alexander of Aphrodisias (c. A.D. 200); cf. Dox. p. 112 sqq. We thus possess a very considerable portion of the First Book, which dealt with the archai, as well as practically the whole of the last Book.
From these remains it clearly appears that the method of Theophrastus was to discuss in separate books the leading topics which had engaged the attention of philosophers from Thales to Plato. The chronological order was not observed; the philosophers were grouped according to the affinity of their doctrine, the differences between those who appeared to agree most closely being carefully noted. The First Book, however, was in some degree exceptional; for in it the order was that of the successive schools, and short historical and chronological notices were inserted.
A work of this kind was, of course, a godsend to the epitomators and compilers of handbooks, who flourished more and more as the Greek genius declined. These either followed Theophrastus in arranging the subject-matter under heads, or else they broke up his work, and rearranged his statements under the names of the various philosophers to whom they applied. This latter class form the natural transition between the doxographers proper and the biographers, so I have ventured to distinguish them by the name of biographical doxographers.
These are now mainly represented by two works, viz. the Placita Philosophorum, included among the writings ascribed to Plutarch, and the Eclogae Physicae of John Stobaeus (c. A.D. 470). The latter originally formed one work with the Florilegium of the same author, and includes a transcript of some epitome substantially identical with the pseudo-Plutarchean Placita. It is, however, demonstrable that neither the Placita nor the doxography of the Eclogae is the original of the other. The latter is usually the fuller of the two, and yet the former must be earlier; for it was used by Athenagoras for his defence of the Christians in A.D. I77 (Dox. p. 4). It was also the source of the notices in Eusebius and Cyril, and of the History of Philosophy ascribed to Galen. From these writers many important corrections of the text have been derived (Dox. pp. 5 sqq.).
Another writer who made use of the Placita is Achilles (not Achilles Tatius). For his Eisagôgê to the Phaenomena of Aratus see Maass, Commentariorum in Aratum reliquiae, pp. 25-75. His date is uncertain, but probably he belongs to the third century A.D. (Dox. p. 18).
What, then, was the common source of the Placita and the Eclogae? Diels has shown that Theodoret (c. A.D. 445) had access to it; for in some cases he gives a fuller form of statements made in these two works. Not only so, but he also names that source; for he refers us (Gr. aff. cur. iv. 31) to Aetiou tên peri areskontôn sunagôgên. Diels has accordingly printed the Placita in parallel columns with the relevant parts of the Eclogae, under the title of Aetii Placita. The quotations from "Plutarch" by later writers, and the extracts of Theodoret from Aetius, are also given at the foot of each page.
Diels has shown further, however, that Aetius did not draw directly from Theophrastus, but from an intermediate epitome which he calls the Vetusta Placita, traces of which may be found in Cicero (infra, § 12), and in Censorinus (De die natali), who follows Varro. The Vetusta Placita were composed in the school of Posidonius, and Diels now calls them the Poseidonian Areskonta (Über das phys. System des Straton, p. 2). There are also traces of them in the "Homeric Allegorists."
It is quite possible, by discounting the somewhat unintelligent additions which Aetius made from Epicurean and other sources, to form a pretty accurate table of the contents of the Vetusta Placita (Dox. pp. 181 sqq.), and this gives us a fair idea of the arrangement of the original work by Theophrastus.
So far as what he tells us of the earliest Greek philosophy goes, Cicero must be classed with the doxographers, and not with the philosophers; for he gives us nothing but extracts at second or third hand from the work of Theophrastus. Two passages in his writings fall to be considered under this head, namely, "Lucullus" (Acad. ii.), 118, and De natura deorum, i. 25-41.
(a) Doxography of the "Lucullus." -- This contains a meagre and inaccurately-rendered summary of the various opinions held by philosophers with regard to the archê (Dox. pp. 119 sqq.), and would be quite useless if it did not in one case enable us to verify the exact words of Theophrastus (Chap. I. p. 50, n. 4). The doxography has come through the hands of Cleitomachus, who succeeded Carneades in the headship of the Academy (129 B.C.).
(b) Doxography of the "De natura deorum." -- A fresh light was thrown upon this important passage by the discovery at Herculaneum of a roll containing fragments of an Epicurean treatise, so like it as to be at once regarded as its original. This treatise was at first ascribed to Phaedrus, on the ground of the reference in Epp. ad Att. xiii. 39. 2; but the real title, Philodêmou peri eusebeias, was afterwards restored (Dox. p. 530). Diels, however, has shown (Dox. pp. 122 sqq.) that there is much to be said for the view that Cicero did not copy Philodemus, but that both drew from a common source (no doubt Phaedrus, Peri Theôn) which itself went back to a Stoic epitome of Theophrastus. The passage of Cicero and the relevant fragments of Philodemus are edited in parallel columns by Diels (Dox. pp. 531 sqq.).
Of the "biographical doxographies," the most important is Book I of the Refutation of all Heresies by Hippolytus. This had long been known as the Philosophoumena of Origen; but the discovery of the remaining books, which were first published at Oxford in 1854, showed finally that it could not belong to him. It is drawn mainly from some good epitome of Theophrastus, in which the matter was already rearranged under the names of the various philosophers. We must note, however, that the sections dealing with Thales, Pythagoras, Heraclitus, and Empedocles come from an inferior source, some merely biographical compendium full of apocryphal anecdotes and doubtful statements.
The fragments of the pseudo-Plutarchean Stromateis, quoted by Eusebius in his Praeparatio Evangelica, come from a source similar to that of the best portions of the Philosophoumena. So far as we can judge, they differ chiefly in two points. In the first place, they are mostly taken from the earliest sections of the work, and therefore most of them deal with the primary substance, the heavenly bodies and the earth. In the second place, the language is a much less faithful transcript of the original.
The scrap-book which goes by the name of Diogenes Laertius, or Laertius Diogenes (cf. Usener, Epicurea, pp. i sqq.), contains large fragments of two distinct doxographies. One is of the merely biographical, anecdotic, and apophthegmatic kind used by Hippolytus in his first four chapters; the other is of a better class, more like the source of Hippolytus' remaining chapters. An attempt is made to disguise this "contamination" by referring to the first doxography as a "summary" (kephalaiôdês) account, while the second is called "particular" (epi merous).
Short doxographical summaries are to be found in Eusebius (P. E. x., xiv., xv.), Theodoret (Gr. aff. cur. ii. 9-11), Irenaeus (C. haer. ii. 14), Arnobius (Adv. nat. ii. 9), Augustine (Civ. Dei, viii. 2). These depend mainly upon the writers of "Successions," whom we shall have to consider in the next section.
The first to write a work entitled Successions of the Philosophers was Sotion (Diog. ii. 12; R. P. 4 a), about 200 B.C. The arrangement of his work is explained in Dox. p. 147. It was epitomised by Heraclides Lembos. Other writers of Diadochai were Antisthenes, Sosicrates, and Alexander. All these compositions were accompanied by a very meagre doxography, and made interesting by the addition of unauthentic apophthegms and apocryphal anecdotes.
The peripatetic Hermippus of Smyrna, known as Callimacheus (c. 200 B.C.), wrote several biographical works which are frequently quoted. The biographical details are very untrustworthy; but sometimes bibliographical information is added, which doubtless rests upon the Pinakes of Callimachus.
Another peripatetic, Satyrus, the pupil of Aristarchus, wrote (c. 16O B.C.) Lives of Famous Men. The same remarks apply to him as to Hermippus. His work was epitomised by Heraclides Lembos.
The work which goes by the name of Laertius Diogenes is, in its biographical parts, a mere patchwork of all earlier learning. It has not been digested or composed by any single mind at all, but is little more than a collection of extracts made at haphazard. But, of course, it contains much that is of the greatest value.
21. Eratosthenes and Apollodorus
The founder of ancient chronology was Eratosthenes of Cyrene (275-194 B.C.); but his work was soon supplanted by the metrical version of Apollodorus (c. 140 B.C.), from which most of our information as to the dates of early philosophers is derived. See Diels' paper on the Chronika of Apollodorus in Rhein. Mus. xxxi.; and Jacoby, Apollodors Chronik (1902).
The method adopted is as follows: -- If the date of some striking event in a philosopher's life is known, that is taken as his floruit (akmê), and he is assumed to have been forty years old at that date. In default of this, some historical era is taken as the floruit. Of these the chief are the eclipse of Thales 586/5 B.C., the taking of Sardis in 546/5 B.C., the accession of Polycrates in 532/1 B.C., and the foundation of Thourioi in 444/3 B.C. It is usual to attach far too much weight to these combinations, and we can often show that Apollodorus is wrong from our other evidence. His dates can only be accepted as a makeshift, when nothing better is available.